From Community Standards to an Ethical Position
Is Animal Experimentation Justified?


Table of Contents

1. Introduction
1.1. Why Community Standards?
1.2. Historical Perspective
1.3. The Current Debate

2. Methods
2.1. Facts
2.2. Values
2.3. Practical
2.4. Logic

3. Premises
3.1. Facts
3.2. Values
     Inherent Rights
     Principle of Equal Consideration
     Public Opinions
     The Law

3.3. Practical Questions

4. Logic
4.1. Rights versus Welfare
4.2. Rights and Protection
4.3. Rights and Obligation
4.4. The Able-to-Assert Argument
4.5. The Kind Argument
4.6. The Kinship Argument
4.7. Criteria Based on Relevant Attributes
4.8. Equality
4.9. Inherent Rights
4.10. Practical Questions

5. Conclusion
5.1. Is Animal Experimentation Justified
5.2. Justifications for the Use of Animals in Research

6. Summary

Appendix – Virginia Anti-Cruelty Law

References


1. Introduction

The problems in the use of nonhuman animals in experiments can be gleaned from the following three quotes. The first is by Adrian R. Morrison; in a lecture on the use of animals in science, he stated that “we are a species unique in our cognitive abilities. . . I think it follows that we owe it to our fellow man to alleviate pain and misery through biomedical research” (17). This view justifies animal use in biomedical research by its benefits to human for the reason that humans are superior. One the other hand, Peter Singer, in his response to Richard R. Vance’s 1993 article in JAMA, contended that “one cannot justify our present assumption that all human beings simply by virtue of their species membership, posses a moral status superior to that of any nonhuman animal” (28). The benefits to human and the exploitation of nonhuman animals (hereafter, animals) create a moral dilemma which we should not overlook. Another dilemma is reflected in a statement in a 1995 handbook of laboratory animal management and welfare, “the justification for using the animal depends on it being different from the human, while the validity of the results obtained depends on the similarity of the animals and their response to those of the human” (31). This observation highlights the conflict between moral judgment and scientific validity in animal research.

Based on my observations and personal experience, even ardent animal advocates understand the benefits, and its accompanying dilemma, in using animals in biomedical research. Often it is their last hurdle in rejecting animal exploitation in general.

I shall explore the moral dilemma in animal experimentation and arrive at an ethical position based on our community standards.


1.1. Why Community Standards?

The debate on animal experimentation invariably starts with a premise based on whether animals have rights. If they are presupposed to have rights, the debate will focus on whether the quality of their rights precludes them from being used in research; otherwise, without the presumption of rights, the debate will focus on our degree of obligation to their welfare. In order to avoid being mired in the discussion of moral theories of rights, and their validity, and detailed utilitarian analysis, I shall take the relativistic approach by limiting the premise for my eventual position to current community standards where the frame of reference of the debate is readily available.


1.2. Historical Perspective

Although Claude Bernard (1813-1878), who was widely considered to be the father of experimental physiology, instituted the paradigm of methodical animal use in biomedicine (14), the general use of animals and its debate dates back to antiquity. Aristotle (384-322 B.C.) wrote in Politics of the importance of the soul over the body and it as the justification for a caste system where a man is superior to his wife, and masters over animals and slaves “for both their bodies minister to the need of life" (23). Saint Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), a theologian and philosophy well known for his commentaries of Aristotle’s works, wrote in his Summa Theologica that “according to the divine ordinance the life of animals and plants is preserved not for themselves but for men”. He also stated that animals, being irrational creatures, cannot form friendship without which happiness cannot be attained; and without happiness charity is impossible; “therefore we cannot have the friendship of charity towards an irrational creature” (23).

French Philosopher René Descartes (1596-1650) in his Discourse on Method focused on the lack of language ability of animals as the justification for their use. He believed that animals are automata because they do not speak and that speech is the only certain sign of thought (23). Voltaire (1694-1778) in his reply to Descartes rejected the assertion that animals are machines. He asked his readers to judge the sentience of animals not by their speech but by observing their actions – their ability to learn, to cry and their friendship with humans (23). German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), a deontologist who whereas believes that human must not treat other humans as means to their end, believes that animals are “not self-conscious and are there merely as a means to an end” and that end is the interest of man. As a result, our duties to animals are indirect, rather than direct, and that the value of animals is in their service to men. He held that we must practice kindness to animals, for “he who is cruel to animals becomes hard also in his dealing with men” (23).

English philosopher Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), one of the founders of utilitarianism, advocated legal rights for animals in The Principle of Morals and Legislation (1789); he recognized the parallel between the exploitation of slaves and animals, and the irrelevance of the criteria use to justify such exploitation. He declared that “the question is not, Can they reason? Nor, Can they talk? But, Can they suffer?” (23)

The idea that social contracts form the basis of rights has been in existence since Plato. The problem is that it is not bound by elementary justice; only the parties who participated in the contract have moral rights and those that they exclude do not. John Rawls (1921-2002) in his A Theory of Justice set forth an interpretation of contractarianism (Rawlsian) which aimed to remove the discriminatory element of simple contractarianism, such as racial discrimination. He held that when we agree on a contract we must be blinded to the personal characteristics that make the contractors different, which he called a “veil of ignorance”. However, according to Rawls, there is a requirement the must be met by the contractors; it is the sense of justice, which in effect eliminates animals from our moral community (7, 24).

As we have seen, for over 2000 years obstacles were erected to exclude animals from having moral-standings, be it the soul, language, reason, fellowship, self-consciousness or the sense of justice.


1.3. The Current Debate

The modern animal debate started in the 1975 with Peter Singer’s seminal work, Animal Liberation (26), where he took a preference-utilitarian perspective. He argued that in assessing the consequence of our actions affecting animals, the interest of the animals must be taken into account; that we must accord equal interest to equal consideration without species bias. However, humans consider themselves to have a superior moral status than animals, thus devaluing their interests. He called such attitude Speciesism.

Utilitarian arguments advocating the use of animals in research is represented by R. G. Frey (11). Although he rejects the liberation of animals, he believes that animals have moral-standing because pain and suffering counts morally, and that life has some value. However, he argues that not all lives, including human lives, have the same value and that a life has value only if it has quality. He concludes that certain humans as well as animals may be used in experimentation.

Tom Regan, on the other hand, is an abolitionist who rejects the utilitarian approach in ethical arguments in general and its use in animal advocacy in particular. He takes the deontological approach and argues that one must respect an individual’s inherent rights; one may not use the holder of such rights merely as means for public interest. He introduces the concept of the subject-of-a-life; any animal that is a subject-of-a-life has inherent right and thus must not be use as instrument of experimentation (7, 21 and 24).

Carl Cohen entered the animal debate in 1986 advocating the use of animals in research in an article that appeared in The New England Journal of Medicine (6). Like Regan, Cohen recognizes the importance of inherent right in the debate in animal experimentation. He believes that if animals have rights, then we must not use them in experiment; however he argues that animals do not and cannot have rights (6, 7).

From the legal perspective Steven M. Wise advocates legal right for animals (29). He reported on researches in the treatment and cognitive abilities of nonhuman primates. Based on the results, he advocates the assignment of autonomy values to species of animals as a framework to provide animals assess to our justice system (30).

Legal scholar and animal rights advocate, Gary Francione coined the term moral schizophrenia in describing the inconsistent nature of our attitude towards animals. He argues that our legal system is ineffective in protecting them as long as they are considered property and merely as the means to human ends (8). He is an animal rightist who criticizes today’s animal welfare movement, which he called the “new welfarism”, as counterproductive (9). Instead, he believes that animals has negative rights — such as the right to be left alone — and calls for the eradication of their property status (10).

Lewis Petrinovich took a sociobiological approach and applies evolutionary principles to reject the positions of Peter Singer and Tom Regan, and to justify the use of animals, including in research (19).


2. Methods

In order to arrive at an ethical position on the use of animals in research, I consider four aspects in the argument. This first three are premises that I shall use in reaching a logical conclusion.


2.1. Facts

Empirical data and scientific findings make up one set of premises in my position. They are considered facts and will not be elaborated further.


2.2. Values

Our values are evident from our history, our public opinions and our laws. They are the basis of our community standards.


2.3. Practical Questions

I shall also consider as premises the benefit and harm of animal experimentation to humans.


2.4. Logic

From the above premises, I shall logically conclude with an ethical position on the use of animals as instrument in research.


3. Premises

In this section I list the premises used in the arguments. Those based on community standards are community values, public opinions and laws.


3.1. Facts

I shall make several assertions here without further discussion or elaboration; they are based on scientific findings and are generally accepted as facts. Supported by mounting evidence and public opinions, animals have the ability to feel pain and to suffer. They have an interest in their physical security, which includes their inclination for life, the avoidance of pain and suffering and their aversion to confinement. Other current findings, which are not essential in reaching the final position, are the presence of cognition and emotion, etc, in animals.

Another category of facts are the body of data obtained from public opinion polls, which is discussed in the following section.


3.2. Values

Our values are the basis for our community standards. Although religion and tradition are important elements of our values and have been used to argue positions in animal use (22), they are not explicitly considered here. Whereas religion and tradition play a key role in shaping our opinions, they are implicit in our concept of rights, public opinions and the law, as well as individual moral judgments.

Inherent Rights

Our value system places emphasis on rights. According to Bernard E. Rollins, “rights are a protection for the individual against the general welfare”; he elaborates and characterizes a right as “a safeguard of the moral status of the individual and his human nature or telos against the pressures of social convenience and general welfare that might otherwise tend to submerge his individuality and crucial interests” (25). Some rights are bestowed upon an individual by virtue of its membership in a community; for example, civil rights. Inherent rights, on the other hand are possessed by the individual by virtue of the individual’s existence. It is generally agreed that inherent rights are the rights of life, bodily integrity and liberty. Liberty refers to the right not to be used merely as means to the end of another individual or the public; liberty includes freedom from slavery or confinement. These rights guarantee the most basic interest, the physical security, of their holder. I shall use this definition as one of my premises.

Autonomy, or self-directing freedom, is not possible without inherent rights. An individual being used merely as a means cannot make choices freely.

What is evident of our inherent rights? In the United States, it is guaranteed in the Declaration of Independence: “We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness”. Countless high court rulings have affirmed this right regardless of physical or mental capacity; a 1992 Massachusetts Supreme Court ruled that “cognitive ability is not a prerequisite for enjoying basic liberties”. Post WWII treaties, agreements and resolutions declare inherent dignity, fundamental freedom and inalienable rights (29).

Principle of Equal Consideration

Another important element of our value system is the principle of equal consideration; it requires that likes must be treated alike. The criterion for unequal treatment must be morally relevant; that is, the criterion used to justify a different treatment must be based on attributes common to both parties and relevant to the issue at hand. This principle is the basis for our opposition to racism, sexism, heterosexism, ageism, ableism, etc, which uses morally irrelevant criterion of group membership to justify exclusion.

Public Opinions

In a widely cited 1995 Associates Press survey, when American respondents were presented with the statement: “Some people say an animal's right to live free of suffering should be just as important as a person's right to live free of suffering”, 38% of them agrees with it strongly and 29% agrees with it somewhat. When asked the same respondents their opinion on the use of animals to test medical treatment, 8% thinks that it is always right while 62% thinks that it is sometimes rights (Figure 1) (2). Other than some exceptions for special demographic groups, similar results were obtained across many polls (3). The polls also suggest that opinions on the use of animals vary depending on the type of research done, the species use and the nature of ownership (Figures 2, 3, 4) (2, 3, 20).

From these data, I conclude that the public believes that animals have some rights, but the nature and quality of right is not specific, except that they should be free of suffering. This attitude towards animals will be one of our premises. I also note that under some circumstances, the public allows the use of animals in medical research.

The Law

The Animal Welfare Act of 1966 was intended to stop the theft of dogs and cats for experimentation. It “prohibits the use of animals if alternatives are feasible”; it requires that “pain be minimized and alternatives considered”; however, it forbids interference in the “the design, outlines, or guidelines of actual research or experimentation” (13).

Most state anticruelty laws acknowledge that animals have certain rights: “The right to nourishment and adequate living condition . . . the right to protection from abandonment . . . the right to protection from poisoning . . . the right to humane transportation”, etc (13). Yet, a number of states include in such laws provisions that exempt such protections for experimentation and for cases where the use is necessary. See appendix A for the Virginia statute (1).

The third aspect is the property status of animals; if it is not stated explicitly by statute, it is implemented in practice by court rulings. As a result, in many cases animal can be used as means when necessary regardless of its welfare, as determined by the owner; the enforcement of animal protection is based on wastefulness of their use as instruments (8). If an animal is wild or is a runaway, the community owns it collectively.


3.3. Practical Questions

Reports of biomedical breakthroughs using animals are numerous. Animal experimentation is instrumental in the development of vaccines, in drug testing, in understanding and developing treatments for diseases such neurodegenerative disorders, in xenografts and in basic sciences.

There are also reports of harms caused by the use of animals in experiments. There are false positive results where drugs that passed animal testing caused harm in human. For example, thalidomide, Opren and AZT were tested with positive results in animals with confidence but was not tested thoroughly in humans. False negatives are less common, but they do occur. In the 1990s, the development of protease inhibitors, a class of AIDS drugs, was delayed for four years because they killed laboratory dogs and rats (12). Humans differ from other animals in genetics and evolutionary history; as a result many human diseases that affect humans but not animals. Alternatives methods such as modeling and stem cell research can be used in place of the use of animals. The paradigm of the animal model in science is so entrenched in our research methods that it may well have erected an obstacle in further seeking alternatives.



4. Logic

Based on the above premises, I shall arrive at an ethical position on the use of animals in research. In order to do so, I divide the inference into a series of arguments, each with its conclusion. The first set of arguments provides a frame of reference for the position; they are:

• The rights versus interest argument
• The rights and protection argument
• The rights and obligations argument

The second set considers conditions that will deny rights for animals:

• The inability in asserting rights
• Membership of the right kind, or the kind argument
• Membership in a community, or the kinship argument

The third set considers the conditions that will affirm rights for animals:

• Relevant Attributes
• Equality
• Inherent Rights

Finally I shall ask the practical question on the validity of the argument in regards to the benefit and harm to humans when animals are relied on as instrument of experimentation.


4.1. Rights versus Welfare

The rights-versus-welfare argument aims to limit the scope of the overall inference to either a deontological or utilitarian approach. The argument that an individual possesses inherent rights is deontological in nature; whereas the idea that an individual does not have inherent rights even though we are obligated to respect their welfare, is utilitarian in approach. This argument is depicted in figure 5.

Utilitarian ethics in its many forms requires that we consider the preference of all parties that are affected by the act, including the parties who commit the immoral, or evil, act. This premise is inconsistent with our moral value and legal standards. We may recognize the inherent rights of a criminal but we do not take their preferences into account in making moral and legal judgments, and in deciding on a punishment. I conclude that the utilitarian approach is unsatisfactory as the basis of in reaching my position on animal experimentation.

Our value system recognizes individual rights as a protection against the pressure of public interest, which in direct conflict with utilitarian ethics. Because of this conflict, we must choose the approach that is in best agreement with our value system. Therefore, we are compelled to recognize the overriding importance of the inherent rights of an individual over public interest. Hereafter the respect for inherent rights forms a basis for our arguments.


4.2. Rights and Protection

Before we go any further, I shall establish the correlation between inherent rights and the protection from use in experimentation. If animals are determined to have inherent rights, it must not be used as means for our end. For example, Carl Cohen embraces this view; however he concluded that animals do not, and cannot, have rights and therefore can be used in experimentation (7).

Inherent rights, as characterized earlier, includes the right of physical security, and the right of not being used merely as means. The second premise is my assertion that the use of an individual, whether it is a human or an animal, involves the violation of life, bodily integrity, which leads to pain and suffering, and the denial of freedom from confinement. From these premises, I conclude that the possession of inherent rights is sufficient for protection from use in experiments, particularly those that violates individual physical security. Research based on the observation of an individual’s behavior in a natural setting; for example, do not violate its inherent rights.

Hereafter, if we determined that animals have inherent rights, then they must not be used as instrument of experimentation.

4.3. Rights and Obligation

For the purpose this argument, I define moral obligation as a demand of conscience, and duties as binding obligations. A direct duty to an individual is a binding obligation to individual, whereas an indirect duty is a binding obligation to a third party who has an interest in the individual. For example, if you have a direct duty to an animal, you must respect the animal’s interest or, if it is determined to possess rights, its rights. On the other hand, if your duty is indirect, you must respect the interest of the owner of the animal, but not necessarily the interests of the animal. In this rights-and-obligation argument, I shall determine whether we owe a duty to protect animals; and if we do, whether the duty is direct or indirect. If our duty, which is binding, is direct, then it is my contention that animals have some rights, although not necessarily inherent rights. This argument is depicted in figure 6.

First, according to our community standards, we have a moral obligation to protect animals. Although some thinkers believe that obligation correlates to rights (4), I am not convinced that it must be so. So on the basis of moral obligations alone, humans do not necessarily owe a duty to animals; humans may respect the welfare but not necessarily the rights of animals. Second, as an application of our community standards, we are legally obligated to protect animals; legal obligation is binding and thus imposes on humans a duty to animals. Third, a binding duty confers some rights to animals, but the rights are not necessarily inherent. Fourth, the legal status of animals is property. Our value system imposes an indirect duty for us to respect others’ properties. These premises lead to the conclusion that humans owe indirect, but not necessarily direct, duties to animals.

Another conclusion can be drawn from this argument. Because the social as well as legal status of animals is property and, according to our value system, an individual with inherent rights cannot be property, I conclude that this inconsistency follows that if animals are determined to have inherent rights, their property status must be abandoned.


4.4. The Able-to-Assert Argument

At this point I have established that if animals are determined to have inherent rights, their use for experimentation must cease. Here I shall consider one of the arguments that are frequently used by animal-use advocates to exclude animals from having rights. As depicted in figure 7, it states that in order for an individual to possess rights, it must be able to assert it. We call the individual a moral agent. Conversely, the inability to assert rights is a sufficient criterion to deny an individual its rights. However not all human can assert rights, they include infants and those with severe mental deficiency, whom we call moral patients. Our value system recognizes inherent rights of all humans, which is inconsistent with the premise. The only conclusion that can be drawn from this argument is that it is invalid. Similar premises include the ability to comprehend rights, which can be invalidated with the same logic.


4.5. The Kind Argument

If the inability to assert rights is an invalid criterion in denying rights for animals, then is the membership of a kind that can assert rights a valid criterion? The argument is depicted in figure 8 as follows:

  1. A is of kind K.
  2. At least some members of K have attribute X.
  3. On the basis of having X, the members have attribute Y.
  4. A have attribute Y.
This argument can be restated in the context of the assertion of rights as follows. Humankind (K) has the attribute of the ability to assert rights (X); on the basis of this attribute, humans have rights (Y). If an individual (A) is of the humankind, then it has rights (Y) even though it cannot assert its rights (X). This is a logical fallacy and therefore is invalid as an argument to deny animals their rights. Similar premises include the membership of a kind that devises the concept of rights; these premises can be invalidated with similar arguments. Nathan Nobis, in a reply to Carl Cohen’s use of this argument (7), further used the same argument to show that all animals have rights and humans do not have rights (18).


4.6. The Kinship Argument

Now that the membership of a kind is an invalid criterion, is membership in a community a valid criterion? That is, are humans morally entitled to treatment animals differently based only the species membership alone. The kinship argument, as depicted in figure 9, is the basis for racism, sexism and other discriminatory practices based on group membership. According to the principle of equal considerations, group membership alone is not a relevant criterion; we must choose a valid criterion with a basis relevant to the issue at hand.


4.7. Criteria Based on Relevant Attributes

Here I shall choose one or more attributes common between humans and animals that are relevant and sufficient for the issue at hand, which is the use in experimentation. At this point there are two avenues which lead to the contention that animals must be protected from use in experimentation. We may choose an attribute that is relevant for the possession of inherent rights, or we may choose one that is relevant to the issue at hand, which is animal experiment. The potential attributes are:

  1. Soul (Aristotle)
  2. Language (Descartes)
  3. Sense of justice (Rawlsian Contractarianism)
  4. Sense of morality (Cohen)
  5. Kind and community (Cohen)
  6. Autonomy in the form of an autonomy index (Wise)
  7. Subject-of-a-life (Regan)
  8. Consciousness (Wise)
  9. Self-awareness
  10. Inclination for life
  11. Susceptibility to pain and suffering
  12. Aversion to confinement.

I reject items 1 to 5 as relevant attributes; the reasons for some of them were discussed earlier. Items 6 to 9 are valid possibilities; however some of them are controversial while others are new concepts that are generally unknown to our community. Items 10 to 12, the inclination for life, susceptibility to pain and suffering and aversion to confinement are attributes that are both commonly accepted and relevant to being used in experimentation. As discussed earlier, these attributes make up the basic interest of physical security for animal, human and nonhuman.


4.8. Equality

Here I choose the susceptibility to suffering as a relevant attribute for the argument; inclination for life and aversion to confinement are equally relevant attributes depending on the experiment performed.

  1. Humans must not use other humans for experiments because humans can suffer.
  2. According to the principle of equal consideration, we must choose the same criterion for nonhuman animals.
  3. Animals can suffer.
  4. Conclusion. Humans must not use animals for experiments.

Based on the principle of equal consideration alone, and without the determination of inherent rights for animals, I conclude that animals must not be used as instrument of experimentation.


4.9. Inherent Rights

Although I have reach an ethical position using the principle of equal consideration as a premise, there are advantages in determining the rights status of animals. The principle of equal consideration requires that we choose a relevant criterion to determine the validity of a discriminating treatment. The possession of inherent rights, on the other hand, guarantees that an individual must not be used as means to the end of the public. We have established that:

  1. Animals have interests in their physical security – life, bodily integrity and liberty. This premise is a presumed fact.
  2. We must not used animals as instruments of research that violates their physical security – life, bodily integrity and liberty . This is a conclusion from the equality argument.
  3. Based on these two statements, I conclude that we must not violate animals’ physical security.
  4. The interests in physical security are the most basic interest. This premise is based on the definition of physical security.
  5. From statement 3 and 4, I conclude that we must protect animals’ most basic interest.
  6. Our community believes that animals do have some rights. This statement of value is determined from public opinions.
  7. From statements 5 and 6, I conclude that if animals have some rights, at the minimum, those rights must be able to protect their most the basic interest. As a result, the interest conveys to rights.
  8. Elements of inherent rights are life, liberty and liberty. This premise our community value.

    From statements 7 and 8, I conclude the rights that we must protect are inherent rights. Therefore animals do have inherent rights.


4.10. Practical Questions

Although I have determined that animal experimentation is morally wrong, there are practical questions that must be answered. That is, are its benefits or harm to humans sufficient reasons in justifying or rejecting animal-use?

First I shall take the utilitarian approach. According to the premises, animal experimentation can both benefit and harm humans. Some benefits by themselves are not sufficient to justify animal experimentation, just as some harm by itself are not sufficient to reject it. Utilitarian ethics requires that they be weighed as part of the scheme in making moral judgments. However the result derived from this method is irrelevant because, according to our earlier conclusion, inherent rights of animals are overriding.

This leaves us with the deontological approach and, according to such approach, public benefit and public harm to the public are not necessary as criteria.


5. Conclusion

5.1. Is Animal Experimentation Justified?

I have arrived at a position base on deontological libertarian ethics; that is, animals have at least inherent rights, which is a negative right: the right to be left alone. As derived from our community standards, animals have inherent rights and therefore it is morally wrong to use animals as instruments of experimentation. However, their possession of inherent rights is not a necessary criterion to reject their use in experiments; the principle of equal considerations is a sufficient premise. On the other hand, there is value in the possession of inherent rights; it guarantees protection against interests of humans, whereas the principle of equal protection requires determination of relevant criteria in a case by case basis.

I also conclude that the property status of animals is inconsistent with their possession of inherent rights and therefore it must be abandoned.


5.2. Justifications for the Use of Animals in Research

Now that we have concluded that animal experimentation has no ethical basis, then under what basis do we, in practice, justifies it? One of the reasons is self-interest. Such interest is not necessarily a mere preference but could be crucial to the welfare of human. For example, you or your child may need an organ transplant and the only way to get it is for another person to die. Although it is immoral to wish death on another person, it is understandable under the circumstances. Our value system forbids taking the life of one person to save another person; in fact, it forbids the taking of one life to save ten others, for example. According to our deontologically based community standards, if an action is determined to be wrong, it must not be allowed.

Another reason is convenience, animals are readily available and they are our property. However, we can easily reject this justification with the same argument as above. Furthermore, if animals have rights, convenience is not a justification because a right is a safeguard of an individual against the pressures of social convenience and general welfare.

Lastly, tradition is commonly used to justification the use of animals in general, many court rulings has allowed the customary use of animals even though it violates the spirit of anti-cruelty laws. It has been demonstrated historically that traditions and customs are irrelevant reasons to continue an action that is determined to be unethical. Again, if the property status of animals is eradicated, this and all justifications of animal instrumentalization become invalid.


6. Summary

In the argument to arrive at the position on the use of animals in research I selected premises based on our community standards. From that I determined the morally correct approach is deontological, where inherent rights have overriding importance. Then I invalidated some of the arguments used to deny inherent rights to animals. Using the principle of equal consideration, I concluded that use of animals as instruments of research is morally wrong and that animals possess inherent rights. Inherent rights are negative rights; so at the minimum we should leave animals alone. The property status of animals is an obstacle for humans to respect the animal rights; it is a moral necessity to abandon such obstacle.


Appendix – Virginia Anti-Cruelty Law

Code OF VIRGINIA
TITLE 3.1. AGRICULTURE, HORTICULTURE AND FOOD
CHAPTER 27.4. COMPREHENSIVE ANIMAL LAWS.
ARTICLE 6. CRUELTY TO ANIMALS.
§ 3.1-796.122. Cruelty to animals; penalty

A. Any person who (i) overrides, overdrives, overloads, tortures, ill-treats, abandons, willfully inflicts inhumane injury or pain not connected with bona fide scientific or medical experimentation, or cruelly or unnecessarily beats, maims, mutilates, or kills any animal, whether belonging to himself or another; (ii) deprives any animal of necessary food, drink, shelter or emergency veterinary treatment; (iii) sores any equine for any purpose or administers drugs or medications to alter or mask such soring for the purpose of sale, show, or exhibition of any kind, unless such administration of drugs or medications is within the context of a veterinary client-patient relationship and solely for therapeutic purposes; (iv) willfully sets on foot, instigates, engages in, or in any way furthers any act of cruelty to any animal; (v) carries or causes to be carried in or upon any vehicle, vessel or otherwise any animal in a cruel, brutal, or inhumane manner, so as to produce torture or unnecessary suffering; or (vi) causes any of the above things, or being the owner of such animal permits such acts to be done by another, shall be guilty of a Class 1 misdemeanor.

B. Any person who (i) tortures, willfully inflicts inhumane injury or pain not connected with bona fide scientific or medical experimentation, or cruelly and unnecessarily beats, maims, mutilates or kills any animal whether belonging to himself or another; (ii) sores any equine for any purpose or administers drugs or medications to alter or mask such soring for the purpose of sale, show, or exhibit of any kind, unless such administration of drugs or medications is under the supervision of a licensed veterinarian and solely for therapeutic purposes; (iii) instigates, engages in, or in any way furthers any act of cruelty to any animal set forth in clause (i); or (iv) causes any of the actions described in clauses (i) through (iii), or being the owner of such animal permits such acts to be done by another; and has been within five years convicted of a violation of this subsection or subsection A, shall be guilty of a Class 6 felony if the current violation or any previous violation of this subsection or subsection A resulted in the death of an animal or the euthanasia of an animal based on the recommendation of a licensed veterinarian upon determination that such euthanasia was necessary due to the condition of the animal, and such condition was a direct result of a violation of this subsection or subsection A.

C. Nothing in this section shall be construed to prohibit the dehorning of cattle.

D. For the purposes of this section and §§ 3.1-796.111, 3.1-796.113, 3.1-796.114, 3.1-796.115, and 3.1-796.125, the word animal shall be construed to include birds and fowl.

E. This section shall not prohibit authorized wildlife management activities or hunting, fishing or trapping as regulated under other titles of the Code of Virginia, including, but not limited to Title 29.1, or to farming activities as provided under this title or regulations promulgated thereto.

F. In addition to the penalties provided in subsection A, the court may, in its discretion, require any person convicted of a violation of subsection A to attend an anger management or other appropriate treatment program or obtain psychiatric or psychological counseling. The court may impose the costs of such a program or counseling upon the person convicted.

G. It is unlawful for any person to kill a domestic dog or cat for the purpose of obtaining the hide, fur or pelt of the dog or cat. A violation of this subsection shall constitute a Class 1 misdemeanor. A second or subsequent violation of this subsection shall constitute a Class 6 felony.

H. Any person who (i) tortures, willfully inflicts inhumane injury or pain not connected with bona fide scientific or medical experimentation or cruelly and unnecessarily beats, maims or mutilates any dog or cat that is a companion animal whether belonging to him or another and (ii) as a direct result causes the death of such dog or cat that is a companion animal, or the euthanasia of such animal on the recommendation of a licensed veterinarian upon determination that such euthanasia was necessary due to the condition of the animal, shall be guilty of a Class 6 felony. The provisions of this subsection shall not overrule § 3.1-796.93:1 or § 3.1-796.116.

I. Any person convicted of violating this section may be prohibited by the court from possession or ownership of companion animals.


References

  1. Animal Rights Law Project. Rutgers University School of Law. Available at:
    http://www.animal-law.org/

  2. Associated Press Poll: Animal right-to-life, 1995. ICR Survey Research Group of Media, Pa., part of AUS Consultants. Available at: http://www.api4animals.org/575print.htm or http://www2.imsa.edu/programs/pbln/problems/geese/pollresults.html

  3. Attitudes towards Animals and Animal Issues. Center for Animals and Public Policy, Tuft University School of Veterinary Medicine. Available at: http://www.tufts.edu/vet/cfa/surveys.html

  4. Beauchamp, Tom L. (1997). “Opposing Views on Animal Experimentation: Do Animals Have Rights?” Ethics and Behavior. Special Issue: Ethical Issues in the Use of Animals in Research. 7(2) 113-121.

  5. Armstrong, S.J., Botzler R. (2003). The Animal Ethics Reader. London: Routledge.

  6. Cohen, Carl. (1986). “The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research”. The New England Journal of Medicine. 352(14) 865-869.
    Reprinted in: Baird R.M., Rosenbaum S.E, ed. (1991). Animal Experimentation, the Moral Issues. Buffalo: Prometheus Books.

  7. Cohen, Carl, and Regan, Tom. (2001). The Animal Rights Debate. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

  8. Francione, Gary. (1995). Animals, Property, and the Law. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

  9. Francione, Gary. (1996). Rain without Thunder: The Ideology of the Animal Rights Movement. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

  10. Francione, Gary. (2000). Introduction to Animal Rights: Your Child or the Dog? Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

  11. Frey R. G. (1997). “Moral Community and Animal Research in Medicine”. Ethics and Behavior. Special Issue: Ethical Issues in the Use of Animals in Research. 7(2) 123-136.

  12. Tatchell, Peter. (1997). Animal Experimentation has hindered AIDS Research. In Animal Experimentation. Haugen David M., book editor. (2000). San Diego: Greenhaven Press.

  13. Jasper, Margaret C. (1997). Animal Rights Law. Dobbs Ferry: Oceana.

  14. LaFollate, Hugh and Shanks, Niall. (1994). Animals Experimentation: The Legacy of Claude Bernard. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 8(3) 195-210.

  15. LaFollate, Hugh and Shanks, Niall. (1996). The Origin of Speciesism. Philosophy. 71 41-61.

  16. Monamy, Vaughan (2000). Animal Experimentation: A Guide to the Issues. Cambridge University Press.

  17. Morrison, Adrian R. (2002). Developing an Ethical View on the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research. The Physiologist. 45(3) 135.

  18. Nobis, Nathan. (2004). Carl Cohen’s ‘Kind’ Arguments For Animal Rights and Against Human Rights. Journal of Applied Philosophy. 21(1).

  19. Peterinovich, Peter (1999). Darwinian Dominion: Animal Welfare and Human Interest. Cambridge: Bradford, MIT Press.

  20. Plous, S. (1996). Attitudes toward the Use of Animals in Psychological Research and Education. American Psychologist. 51(11) ,1167-1180.

  21. Regan, Tom (1983). The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  22. Regan, Tom, ed. (1986). Animal Sacrifices: Religious Perspectives on the use of Animals in Science. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

  23. Regan, Tom, and Peter Singer, ed. (1989). Animal Rights and Human Obligations, 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

  24. Regan, Tom (2004). Empty Cages: Facing the Challenge of Animal Rights. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

  25. Rollins, Bernard E. (1981). Animal Rights and Human Morality. New York: Prometheus Books.

  26. Singer, Peter. (2002) Animal Liberation. New York: HarperCollins.

  27. Sunstein, C.R, and Nussbaum, M.C. (2004). Animal Rights: Current Debate and New Directions. Oxford University Press.

  28. Vance, Richard P. (1992). An Introduction to the Philosophical Presupposition of the Animal Liberation/Rights Movement. JAMA. 268(13) 1715-1719.
    Responses from Rowan, Andrew N., Singer, Peter, Regan, Tom and Vance, Richard P. (1993). Is Justification of Animal Research Necessary? JAMA. 169(9), 1113-1115.

  29. Wise, Steven M. (2000). Rattling the Cage: Toward Legal Rights for Animals. Cambridge: Perseus.

  30. Wise, Steven M. (2002). Drawing the Line: Science and the Case for Animal Rights. Cambridge: Perseus.

  31. Wolfensohn, S. and Lloyd, M. (1995). Handbook of Laboratory Animal Management and Welfare. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  32.  

Copyright © 2005 by Clayton Fan